35 pages • 1 hour read
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
In peaceful times, those who are most prone to war will end up going to war with themselves; certain individuals can’t help but to be constantly at odds with something in the world.
When a common sympathy is felt for all in a forced manner in which all are to be treated precisely the same, it tends to destroy the more naturally felt bonds of charity for one’s neighbor, for whom one naturally feels more connected than a common stranger.
In discovering that another has fallen in love with one, says Nietzsche, this discovery should at once bring with it the feeling of revulsion for the simple fact that this person could only be deluded for falling in love in this manner.
Evil will likely rub off on those spending time in its presence. The more one looks into the darkness, the more the darkness is likely to seep into one’s consciousness and leave a lasting impression.
Current ideals and morality always tend to come and go in waves. The evils of one age always tend to be in direct proportion to the ideals and morals of the previous generation. Old ideals die hard, and the generation that is raised with a particular perspective on what is meant to be good and desirable will often reject these very same ideals as the involuntary imposition of a bygone age.
Contrary to popular belief, the various systems of morality have not in fact been concerned with morality as such. Morality as it is all too often construed is much more about the preservation of the current trends in ethics rather than the science of attempting what is truly good and moral in the first place. It is a kind of faith or belief in the morality to which the majority of contemporary society adheres. The assertions of various moral philosophers who attempt to lay down various rules or systems seem to be attempts to impose whatever morality fits that particular individual; no matter the system, regardless of the ultimate goal, the moral system is “a sign-language of the emotions” (86).
For centuries past, the thinkers on the European continent went about their philosophy with the result already in mind, the end goal already set, and the system arranged to arrive at that result. On top of this general direction in which the outcomes are set and molded, the European mindset is arranged such that they are addicted to work, so the religious instinct to establish sabbath days—where work is stopped—is an ingenious plan to force them into desiring the work of the week.
This instinct is then set against what we call reason, pitting the emotions against the intellect, which is the true foundation of the “old theological problem” of faith and knowledge. The one who acts according to their inner feelings is following instinct, which is what religion calls faith; this one is set against the one who attempts to act according to pure reason, or according to the knowledge of which they are sure. Ever since the time of Plato’s impact the theologians and philosophers have followed their instincts, which they term faith, which is in fact “the herd” (91). This instinct, unfortunately, has forced the religious into turning their charitable works into manipulation, “they take control of the needy as a property” (94) and bring those to whom they bring relief into their debt. The whole Judeo-Christian system has performed a “miracle of the inversion of valuations” (94) in this transformation of human relations, turning the world into something wicked and violent.
The free spirits, however, will be able to stand against this herd mentality and will have the strength of will to stand on their own, even when they are deemed to be dangerous to themselves and to society. “Morality in Europe at present is herding-animal morality” (103), and this is what the free spirit and the strong-willed must work against, imposing new moralities and new systems that will fit to the truth of reality. This is what is necessary, but “a new type of philosopher and commander will some time or other be needed” (105) to complete this project.
Philosophers and their philosophy are in desperate need of asserting their own significance and their own autonomy. Science and theology have had their day, and it is frustrating that even science has put itself in the place of philosophy after finally conquering theology, but this cannot be allowed to continue; it cannot continue to “play the ‘master’” (108) if society is to continue in its march toward progress. However, it is also the case that a mere catalog of knowledge and thought systems cannot be allowed to masquerade as true philosophy, for too often this philosophy is no more than the collection and regurgitation of knowledge and facts, and this is the very thing that cannot take charge. In this light, philosophy and the real philosophers could never rule, and “one might doubt whether this fruit could still come to maturity” (108) but rather languish in immaturity and in a state or perpetual waiting.
The worst philosopher and scholar is the one who is simply content with their own mediocrity, though this is what is so common in the world of today. Far too many hold to a worldview of skepticism, but even this is not enough and too often simply digresses into a nervous debility that disallows any progress or real action to take place. Throughout modern Europe this is precisely what has occurred; it is skeptical of all things through and through. The only path through this wilderness is to acquire a singular and iron will that will break the mold that has been set, and the “time for petty politics is past; the next century will bring the struggle for the dominion of the world” (116). This will require the greatest of wills.
The general public is too often fooled into collapsing the distinctions between the various kinds of public intellectuals, for the scientists are not the philosophers, who in turn are not the philosophical workers. It is the job of the philosophical workers to “fix and formalize some great existing body of valuations” (123), which is a noble task indeed; however, it is the task of the true philosophers to be “commanders and law-givers” (123), and it is they who will put the force to the wheel that will turn history. It is the knowledge and activity of the philosophers alone who will create the world, their will to power, but it will come at a steep cost. The philosopher will be a martyr, for it is he who “has ever found himself, and has been obliged to find himself, in contradiction to the day in which he lives; his enemy has always been the ideal of his day” (123-24). This also cannot be given, and it cannot be taught; it simply must be learned and known by experience. It is a singular gift and calling and the vocation of the artist is the only thing that comes close to the same ideals and mission.
The fourth chapter is the most enigmatic of Nietzsche’s text, as there is no real through-line holding the chapter together. Rather, it is a collected set of proverbs, thoughts, and pithy sayings that seem to capture the various tangential thoughts of the Nietzschean system but do not find a natural place within the overall arc of the text as a whole. There is no doubt they individually tend to strengthen the reader’s reception of the author’s worldview and philosophy, but a clean summary of the section eludes the analyst.
In any case, although a general outline or theme is lacking, there are nevertheless several important points to be made. One of the most important notes is the denigration of the passion of sympathy, which is most pernicious when it is meant to be felt for all equally. Sympathy is practically a curse word for Nietzsche in the text, but here it is specifically invalid when it is meant to be a universal counsel, an emotion to be felt for every person equally. Nietzsche believes this neurosis disintegrates one’s more natural bonds of affection for one’s neighbor, as a stranger would theoretically have just as great a claim on our resources as a family member or friend.
The second sharp point to be found here is the judgment that ideals and morals come in waves, and this alone is enough to demonstrate that a fixed morality is an illusion. As the author argues, the morals and ideals of one age becomes the intellectual backwater of the age that follows it. A generation raised on a certain set of ideals will inevitably outgrow it and dump it into the trash bin of history as a childish set of rules that can be disposed of once the current age has grown into maturity.
Moving into the fifth chapter, this general vision of ideals and morality as passing in waves is burrowed into with greater vigor as the history of morality and its sources is expounded upon. Nietzsche argues that morality, paradoxically, has never really been concerned with morality per se but with the preservation of a certain a priori ideal that needs to be guarded and protected by a moral system that argues to show it is true. This is the opposite of what should be the case, as morality should be the investigation of the truth and the reality of the matter, and then once certain conclusions are reached, or certain ideals laid out, only then could any morals be spoken of.
Complicating the problem is the ancient problem of faith and reason, of the intellect in competition with the emotions. The religious and the theologians have set their flags on the side of emotions and instinct, which they have cunningly dubbed faith. Rather, it is the intellect and pure reason that must conquer and banish the emotions, an act that the herds of commonfolk are loath to do (and in fact are incapable of doing). The groupthink in which the average person lives guides the masses in one direction, and it is against this tide the free spirits are meant to swim and contradict.
These free spirits, however, are not to be confused with the figures who are commonly recognized as philosophers and scholars. The two could not be more different in the eyes of the author. The theologians and the scientists have had their time in the spotlight and in seats of power, all to no avail. The scientist thought to supplant the theologian, but even science cannot wield the power necessary to change the world. The free spirit is the one who must wield this power over and against the faux philosophers, who weave systems of thought and ethics in an attempt to deceive and convince. This is but a regurgitation of previously discovered knowledge and not true wisdom; it is a state of perpetual infancy, completely reliant on another to enter and take charge.
This mediocrity of the scholars is a plague, and it must be overcome by sheer force of will, the will to power, and it is in the 20th century that the stage of world politics will prove to be the battleground for the competing wills of the great men of the age. Nietzsche believes the general public, of course, is too stupid to realize this and too weak to do anything about it even if they knew the truth. It will be up to the true philosopher, the true free spirit and strong man, to create value and morality on his own by the power of his own will. In this, he plays the part of the artist, bringing existence into being out of nothing but his own mind and will.
Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.
Including features:
By Friedrich Nietzsche